Montaigne: Essays

Guide cover image

53 pages • 1 hour read

Montaigne: Selected Essays

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Translator’s Preface-Book 1, Chapter 21

Book 1, Chapters 26, 28, 31, 39, and 50

Book 2, Chapters 6, 11, and 17

Book 2, Chapters 18, 28, and 30

Book 3, Chapters 2, 12, and 13

“Discourse on Voluntary Servitude”

Key Figures

Symbols & Motifs

Important Quotes

Essay Topics

Discussion Questions

Summary and Study Guide

Montaigne: Selected Essays comes from the pen of Michel de Montaigne , a 16th-century French jurist, advisor, and diplomat whose many adventures would make a compelling autobiography. Instead, Montaigne writes a series of short works that examine his innermost thoughts and feelings, attitudes and beliefs, preferences and daily habits. This would seem a dull topic, but Montaigne’s charm, wit, and wisdom shine through and make the mundane seem fascinating. His attitude is tolerant and open-minded for his era, and his ideas and insights remain relevant today. The essays have entertained and enlightened readers worldwide for over 400 years.

This edition of his book features eighteen of Montaigne’s 107 essays, along with a well-known and influential discourse by Montaigne’s dearest friend, Étienne de la Boétie . The essays were first published as three Books; those chosen for this edition are organized by Book. Most of the essays discuss several topics, but each contains a central theme.

Get access to this full Study Guide and much more!

  • 7,300+ In-Depth Study Guides
  • 4,950+ Quick-Read Plot Summaries
  • Downloadable PDFs

In Book 1, the first essay, “By Differing Means We Attain the Same End,” describes two ways to win mercy after defeat in battle. The second essay, “Idleness,” explores the problem of a wandering mind. The third, “Through Philosophy We Learn How to Die,” suggests a proper attitude toward death. “The Power of the Imagination” shows how superstitions can kill, self-consciousness can defeat, and a doctor’s reassurance can cure.

“The Education of Children” lists Montaigne’s surprisingly modern ideas for how kids should be taught. In the process, we learn his prescription for how to help a young person grow into someone who will lead a worthwhile life.

“Friendship” explores the difference between ordinary companions and true friends. “The Cannibals” suggests that so-called “barbaric” tribes have lessons to teach Europeans. “Democritus and Heraclitus” finds common cause with famous pessimists.

The SuperSummary difference

  • 8x more resources than SparkNotes and CliffsNotes combined
  • Study Guides you won ' t find anywhere else
  • 100+ new titles every month

In Book 2, “Practice” gives tips on how to prepare for death; “Cruelty” talks about how hard it is to be virtuous; “Being Presumptuous” attacks vanity and putting on airs; “Correcting” rails against lying. In “To Everything There Is a Season,” Montaigne scoffs at old men who try to stay young. “A Malformed Child” opines that everything, even the strange or deformed, is part of Nature’s plan.

Three selections come from Book 3: “Repenting”, on the folly of apologizing for who you really are; “Physiognomy,” on the wars and plagues that visit Montaigne’s neighborhood; and “Experience,” which touts the virtues of common sense over fancy ideals.

The final section is the essay “Discourse on Voluntary Servitude,” a call to arms against tyranny that influences revolutionaries and philosophers for centuries. It also affects Montaigne’s thinking, as it comes from the man Montaigne loved most in the world, Étienne de la Boétie.

Montaigne’s style is direct, lively, humorous, and sometimes bawdy and coarse. He wanders from topic to topic in the style of a lively conversation. Though he cites frequently the sayings of ancient philosophers, he also trusts his own judgment, and the gist of the essays is that we, too, should trust ourselves—that life isn’t so much a problem to be solved as an experience to be enjoyed for what it is.

The book’s original French is translated into English for modern Americans; it contains extensive footnotes, many of which provide historical background and serve as annotations well worth consulting.

Editor’s note: This guide refers to the 2012 Hackett Classics edition, translated by James B. Atkinson and Martin Sices.

blurred text

Don't Miss Out!

Access Study Guide Now

Ready to dive in?

Get unlimited access to SuperSummary for only $ 0.70 /week

Featured Collections

Elizabethan era.

View Collection

French Literature

Philosophy, logic, & ethics.

michel de montaigne essays summary

Guide to the classics: Michel de Montaigne’s Essays

michel de montaigne essays summary

Associate Professor in Philosophy, Deakin University

Disclosure statement

Matthew Sharpe is part of an ARC funded project on modern reinventions of the ancient idea of "philosophy as a way of life", in which Montaigne is a central figure.

Deakin University provides funding as a member of The Conversation AU.

View all partners

When Michel de Montaigne retired to his family estate in 1572, aged 38, he tells us that he wanted to write his famous Essays as a distraction for his idle mind . He neither wanted nor expected people beyond his circle of friends to be too interested.

His Essays’ preface almost warns us off:

Reader, you have here an honest book; … in writing it, I have proposed to myself no other than a domestic and private end. I have had no consideration at all either to your service or to my glory … Thus, reader, I myself am the matter of my book: there’s no reason that you should employ your leisure upon so frivolous and vain a subject. Therefore farewell.

The ensuing, free-ranging essays, although steeped in classical poetry, history and philosophy, are unquestionably something new in the history of Western thought. They were almost scandalous for their day.

No one before Montaigne in the Western canon had thought to devote pages to subjects as diverse and seemingly insignificant as “Of Smells”, “Of the Custom of Wearing Clothes”, “Of Posting” (letters, that is), “Of Thumbs” or “Of Sleep” — let alone reflections on the unruliness of the male appendage , a subject which repeatedly concerned him.

French philosopher Jacques Rancière has recently argued that modernism began with the opening up of the mundane, private and ordinary to artistic treatment. Modern art no longer restricts its subject matters to classical myths, biblical tales, the battles and dealings of Princes and prelates.

michel de montaigne essays summary

If Rancière is right, it could be said that Montaigne’s 107 Essays, each between several hundred words and (in one case) several hundred pages, came close to inventing modernism in the late 16th century.

Montaigne frequently apologises for writing so much about himself. He is only a second rate politician and one-time Mayor of Bourdeaux, after all. With an almost Socratic irony , he tells us most about his own habits of writing in the essays titled “Of Presumption”, “Of Giving the Lie”, “Of Vanity”, and “Of Repentance”.

But the message of this latter essay is, quite simply, that non, je ne regrette rien , as a more recent French icon sang:

Were I to live my life over again, I should live it just as I have lived it; I neither complain of the past, nor do I fear the future; and if I am not much deceived, I am the same within that I am without … I have seen the grass, the blossom, and the fruit, and now see the withering; happily, however, because naturally.

Montaigne’s persistence in assembling his extraordinary dossier of stories, arguments, asides and observations on nearly everything under the sun (from how to parley with an enemy to whether women should be so demure in matters of sex , has been celebrated by admirers in nearly every generation.

Within a decade of his death, his Essays had left their mark on Bacon and Shakespeare. He was a hero to the enlighteners Montesquieu and Diderot. Voltaire celebrated Montaigne - a man educated only by his own reading, his father and his childhood tutors – as “the least methodical of all philosophers, but the wisest and most amiable”. Nietzsche claimed that the very existence of Montaigne’s Essays added to the joy of living in this world.

michel de montaigne essays summary

More recently, Sarah Bakewell’s charming engagement with Montaigne, How to Live or a Life of Montaigne in One Question and Twenty Attempts at an Answer (2010) made the best-sellers’ lists. Even today’s initiatives in teaching philosophy in schools can look back to Montaigne (and his “ On the Education of Children ”) as a patron saint or sage .

So what are these Essays, which Montaigne protested were indistinguishable from their author? (“ My book and I go hand in hand together ”).

It’s a good question.

Anyone who tries to read the Essays systematically soon finds themselves overwhelmed by the sheer wealth of examples, anecdotes, digressions and curios Montaigne assembles for our delectation, often without more than the hint of a reason why.

To open the book is to venture into a world in which fortune consistently defies expectations; our senses are as uncertain as our understanding is prone to error; opposites turn out very often to be conjoined (“ the most universal quality is diversity ”); even vice can lead to virtue. Many titles seem to have no direct relation to their contents. Nearly everything our author says in one place is qualified, if not overturned, elsewhere.

Without pretending to untangle all of the knots of this “ book with a wild and desultory plan ”, let me tug here on a couple of Montaigne’s threads to invite and assist new readers to find their own way.

Philosophy (and writing) as a way of life

Some scholars argued that Montaigne began writing his essays as a want-to-be Stoic , hardening himself against the horrors of the French civil and religious wars , and his grief at the loss of his best friend Étienne de La Boétie through dysentery.

michel de montaigne essays summary

Certainly, for Montaigne, as for ancient thinkers led by his favourites, Plutarch and the Roman Stoic Seneca, philosophy was not solely about constructing theoretical systems, writing books and articles. It was what one more recent admirer of Montaigne has called “ a way of life ”.

Montaigne has little time for forms of pedantry that value learning as a means to insulate scholars from the world, rather than opening out onto it. He writes :

Either our reason mocks us or it ought to have no other aim but our contentment.
We are great fools . ‘He has passed over his life in idleness,’ we say: ‘I have done nothing today.’ What? have you not lived? that is not only the fundamental, but the most illustrious of all your occupations.

One feature of the Essays is, accordingly, Montaigne’s fascination with the daily doings of men like Socrates and Cato the Younger ; two of those figures revered amongst the ancients as wise men or “ sages ”.

Their wisdom, he suggests , was chiefly evident in the lives they led (neither wrote a thing). In particular, it was proven by the nobility each showed in facing their deaths. Socrates consented serenely to taking hemlock, having been sentenced unjustly to death by the Athenians. Cato stabbed himself to death after having meditated upon Socrates’ example , in order not to cede to Julius Caesar’s coup d’état .

michel de montaigne essays summary

To achieve such “philosophic” constancy, Montaigne saw, requires a good deal more than book learning . Indeed, everything about our passions and, above all, our imagination , speaks against achieving that perfect tranquillity the classical thinkers saw as the highest philosophical goal.

We discharge our hopes and fears, very often, on the wrong objects, Montaigne notes , in an observation that anticipates the thinking of Freud and modern psychology. Always, these emotions dwell on things we cannot presently change. Sometimes, they inhibit our ability to see and deal in a supple way with the changing demands of life.

Philosophy, in this classical view, involves a retraining of our ways of thinking, seeing and being in the world. Montaigne’s earlier essay “ To philosophise is to learn how to die ” is perhaps the clearest exemplar of his indebtedness to this ancient idea of philosophy.

Yet there is a strong sense in which all of the Essays are a form of what one 20th century author has dubbed “ self-writing ”: an ethical exercise to “strengthen and enlighten” Montaigne’s own judgement, as much as that of we readers:

And though nobody should read me, have I wasted time in entertaining myself so many idle hours in so pleasing and useful thoughts? … I have no more made my book than my book has made me: it is a book consubstantial with the author, of a peculiar design, a parcel of my life …

As for the seeming disorder of the product, and Montaigne’s frequent claims that he is playing the fool , this is arguably one more feature of the Essays that reflects his Socratic irony. Montaigne wants to leave us with some work to do and scope to find our own paths through the labyrinth of his thoughts, or alternatively, to bobble about on their diverting surfaces .

A free-thinking sceptic

Yet Montaigne’s Essays, for all of their classicism and their idiosyncracies, are rightly numbered as one of the founding texts of modern thought . Their author keeps his own prerogatives, even as he bows deferentially before the altars of ancient heroes like Socrates, Cato, Alexander the Great or the Theban general Epaminondas .

michel de montaigne essays summary

There is a good deal of the Christian, Augustinian legacy in Montaigne’s makeup. And of all the philosophers, he most frequently echoes ancient sceptics like Pyrrho or Carneades who argued that we can know almost nothing with certainty. This is especially true concerning the “ultimate questions” the Catholics and Huguenots of Montaigne’s day were bloodily contesting.

Writing in a time of cruel sectarian violence , Montaigne is unconvinced by the ageless claim that having a dogmatic faith is necessary or especially effective in assisting people to love their neighbours :

Between ourselves, I have ever observed supercelestial opinions and subterranean manners to be of singular accord …

This scepticism applies as much to the pagan ideal of a perfected philosophical sage as it does to theological speculations.

Socrates’ constancy before death, Montaigne concludes, was simply too demanding for most people, almost superhuman . As for Cato’s proud suicide, Montaigne takes liberty to doubt whether it was as much the product of Stoic tranquility, as of a singular turn of mind that could take pleasure in such extreme virtue .

Indeed when it comes to his essays “ Of Moderation ” or “ Of Virtue ”, Montaigne quietly breaks the ancient mold. Instead of celebrating the feats of the world’s Catos or Alexanders, here he lists example after example of people moved by their sense of transcendent self-righteousness to acts of murderous or suicidal excess.

Even virtue can become vicious, these essays imply, unless we know how to moderate our own presumptions.

Of cannibals and cruelties

If there is one form of argument Montaigne uses most often, it is the sceptical argument drawing on the disagreement amongst even the wisest authorities.

If human beings could know if, say, the soul was immortal, with or without the body, or dissolved when we die … then the wisest people would all have come to the same conclusions by now, the argument goes. Yet even the “most knowing” authorities disagree about such things, Montaigne delights in showing us .

The existence of such “ an infinite confusion ” of opinions and customs ceases to be the problem, for Montaigne. It points the way to a new kind of solution, and could in fact enlighten us.

Documenting such manifold differences between customs and opinions is, for him, an education in humility :

Manners and opinions contrary to mine do not so much displease as instruct me; nor so much make me proud as they humble me.

His essay “ Of Cannibals ” for instance, presents all of the different aspects of American Indian culture, as known to Montaigne through travellers’ reports then filtering back into Europe. For the most part, he finds these “savages’” society ethically equal, if not far superior, to that of war-torn France’s — a perspective that Voltaire and Rousseau would echo nearly 200 years later.

We are horrified at the prospect of eating our ancestors. Yet Montaigne imagines that from the Indians’ perspective, Western practices of cremating our deceased, or burying their bodies to be devoured by the worms must seem every bit as callous.

And while we are at it, Montaigne adds that consuming people after they are dead seems a good deal less cruel and inhumane than torturing folk we don’t even know are guilty of any crime whilst they are still alive …

A gay and sociable wisdom

michel de montaigne essays summary

“So what is left then?”, the reader might ask, as Montaigne undermines one presumption after another, and piles up exceptions like they had become the only rule.

A very great deal , is the answer. With metaphysics, theology, and the feats of godlike sages all under a “ suspension of judgment ”, we become witnesses as we read the Essays to a key document in the modern revaluation and valorization of everyday life.

There is, for instance, Montaigne’s scandalously demotic habit of interlacing words, stories and actions from his neighbours, the local peasants (and peasant women) with examples from the greats of Christian and pagan history. As he writes :

I have known in my time a hundred artisans, a hundred labourers, wiser and more happy than the rectors of the university, and whom I had much rather have resembled.

By the end of the Essays, Montaigne has begun openly to suggest that, if tranquillity, constancy, bravery, and honour are the goals the wise hold up for us, they can all be seen in much greater abundance amongst the salt of the earth than amongst the rich and famous:

I propose a life ordinary and without lustre: ‘tis all one … To enter a breach, conduct an embassy, govern a people, are actions of renown; to … laugh, sell, pay, love, hate, and gently and justly converse with our own families and with ourselves … not to give our selves the lie, that is rarer, more difficult and less remarkable …

And so we arrive with these last Essays at a sentiment better known today from another philosopher, Friedrich Nietzsche, the author of A Gay Science (1882) .

Montaigne’s closing essays repeat the avowal that: “ I love a gay and civil wisdom … .” But in contrast to his later Germanic admirer, the music here is less Wagner or Beethoven than it is Mozart (as it were), and Montaigne’s spirit much less agonised than gently serene.

It was Voltaire, again, who said that life is a tragedy for those who feel, and a comedy for those who think. Montaigne adopts and admires the comic perspective . As he writes in “Of Experience”:

It is not of much use to go upon stilts , for, when upon stilts, we must still walk with our legs; and when seated upon the most elevated throne in the world, we are still perched on our own bums.
  • Classic literature
  • Michel de Montaigne

michel de montaigne essays summary

Director, Defence and Security

michel de montaigne essays summary

Director, NIKERI Institute

michel de montaigne essays summary

Biocloud Project Manager - Australian Biocommons

michel de montaigne essays summary

Opportunities with the new CIEHF

michel de montaigne essays summary

School of Social Sciences – Public Policy and International Relations opportunities

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

image of Montaigne

François Quesnel, “Montaigne”, c. 1590, drawing reprinted with permission from the Montaigne Studies website

Michel de Montaigne

The question is not who will hit the ring, but who will make the best runs at it.

Given the huge breadth of his readings, Montaigne could have been ranked among the most erudite humanists of the XVI th century. But in the Essays , his aim is above all to exercise his own judgment properly. Readers who might want to convict him of ignorance would find nothing to hold against him, he said, for he was exerting his natural capacities, not borrowed ones. He thought that too much knowledge could prove a burden, preferring to exert his “natural judgment” to displaying his erudition.

3. A Philosophy of Free Judgment

4. montaigne’s scepticism, 5. montaigne and relativism, 6. montaigne’s legacy from charron to hobbes, 7. conclusion, translations in english, secondary sources, translations, related entries.

Montaigne (1533–1592) came from a rich bourgeois family that acquired nobility after his father fought in Italy in the army of King Francis I of France; he came back with the firm intention of bringing refined Italian culture to France. He decorated his Périgord castle in the style of an ancient Roman villa. He also decided that his son would not learn Latin in school. He arranged instead for a German preceptor and the household to speak to him exclusively in Latin at home. So the young Montaigne grew up speaking Latin and reading Vergil, Ovid, and Horace on his own. At the age of six, he was sent to board at the Collège de Guyenne in Bordeaux, which he later praised as the best humanist college in France, though he found fault with humanist colleges in general. Where Montaigne later studied law, or, indeed, whether he ever studied law at all is not clear. The only thing we know with certainty is that his father bought him an office in the Court of Périgueux. He then met Etienne de La Boëtie with whom he formed an intimate friendship and whose death some years later, in 1563, left him deeply distraught. Tired of active life, he retired at the age of only 37 to his father’s castle. In the same year, 1571, he was nominated Gentleman of King Charles IX’s Ordinary Chamber, and soon thereafter, also of Henri de Navarre’s Chamber. He received the decoration of the Order of Saint-Michel, a distinction all the more exceptional as Montaigne’s lineage was from recent nobility. On the title page of the first edition (1580) of the Essays , we read: “Essais de Messire Michel Seigneur de Montaigne, Chevalier de l’ordre du Roy, & Gentilhomme ordinaire de sa chambre.” Initially keen to show off his titles and, thus, his social standing, Montaigne had the honorifics removed in the second edition (1582).

Replicating Petrarca’s choice in De vita solitaria , Montaigne chose to dedicate himself to the Muses. In his library, which was quite large for the period, he had wisdom formulas carved on the wooden beams. They were drawn from, amongst others, Ecclesiastes , Sextus Empiricus, Lucretius, and other classical authors, whom he read intensively. To escape fits of melancholy, he began to commit his thoughts to paper. In 1580, he undertook a journey to Italy, whose main goal was to cure the pain of his kidney stones at thermal resorts. The journey is related in part by a secretary, in part by Montaigne himself, in a manuscript that was only discovered during the XVIII th century, given the title The Journal of the Journey to Italy , and forgotten soon after. While Montaigne was taking the baths near Pisa, he learnt of his election as Mayor of Bordeaux. He was first tempted to refuse out of modesty, but eventually accepted (he even received a letter from the King urging him to take the post) and was later re-elected. In his second term he came under criticism for having abandoned the town during the great plague in an attempt to protect himself and his family. His time in office was dimmed by the wars of religion between Catholics and Protestants. Several members of his family converted to Protestantism, but Montaigne himself remained a Catholic.

Montaigne wrote three books of Essays . (“Essay” was an original name for this kind of work; it became an appreciated genre soon after.) Three main editions are recognized: 1580 (at this stage, only the first two books were written), 1588, and 1595. The last edition, which could not be supervised by Montaigne himself, was edited from the manuscript by his adoptive daughter Marie de Gournay. Till the end of the XIX th century, the copy text for all new editions was that of 1595; Fortunat Strowski and shortly after him Pierre Villey dismissed it in favor of the “Bordeaux copy”, a text of the 1588 edition supplemented by manuscript additions. [ 1 ] Montaigne enriched his text continuously; he preferred to add for the sake of diversity, rather than to correct. [ 2 ] The unity of the work and the order of every single chapter remain problematic. We are unable to detect obvious links from one chapter to the next: in the first book, Montaigne jumps from “Idleness” (I,8) to “Liars” (I,9), then from “Prompt or slow speech” (I,10) to “Prognostications” (I,11). The random aspect of the work, acknowledged by the author himself, has been a challenge for commentators ever since. Part of the brilliance of the Essays lies in this very ability to elicit various forms of explanatory coherence whilst at the same time defying them. The work is so rich and flexible that it accommodates virtually any academic trend. Yet, it is also so resistant to interpretation that it reveals the limits of each interpretation.

Critical studies of the Essays have, until recently, been mainly of a literary nature. However, to consider Montaigne as a writer rather than as a philosopher can be a way of ignoring a disturbing thinker. Indeed, he shook some fundamental aspects of Western thought, such as the superiority we assign to man over animals, [ 3 ] to European civilization over “Barbarians”, [ 4 ] or to reason as an alleged universal standard. A tradition rooted in the 19th century tends to relegate his work to the status of literary impressionism or to the expression of a frivolous subjectivity. To do him justice, one needs to bear in mind the inseparable unity of thought and style in his work. Montaigne’s repeated revisions of his text, as modern editions show with the three letters A, B, C, standing for the three main editions, mirror the relationship between the activity of his thought and the Essays as a work in progress. The Essays display both the laboriousness and the delight of thinking.

In Montaigne we have a writer whose work is deeply infused by philosophical thought. One verse out of sixteen in Lucretius’ De natura rerum is quoted in the Essays . [ 5 ] If it is true, as Edmund Husserl said, that philosophy is a shared endeavor, Montaigne is perhaps the most exemplary of philosophers since his work extensively borrows and quotes from others. Montaigne managed to internalize a huge breadth of reading, so that his erudition does not appear as such. He created a most singular work, yet one that remains deeply rooted in the community of poets, historians, and philosophers. His decision to use only his own judgment in dealing with all sorts of matters, his resolutely distant attitude towards memory and knowledge, his warning that we should not mix God or transcendent principles with the human world, are some of the key elements that characterize Montaigne’s position. As a humanist, he considered that one has to assimilate the classics, but above all to display virtue, “according to the opinion of Plato, who says that steadfastness, faith, and sincerity are real philosophy, and the other sciences which aim at other things are only powder and rouge.” [ 6 ]

Montaigne rejects the theoretical or speculative way of philosophizing that prevailed under the Scholastics ever since the Middle Ages. According to him, science does not exist, but only a general belief in science. Petrarch had already criticized the Scholastics for worshiping Aristotle as their God. Siding with the humanists, Montaigne develops a sharp criticism of science “à la mode des Geométriens”, [ 7 ] the mos geometricus deemed to be the most rigorous. It is merely “a practice and business of science”, [ 8 ] he says, which is restricted to the University and essentially carried out between masters and their disciples. The main problem of this kind of science is that it makes us spend our time justifying as rational the beliefs we inherit, instead of calling into question their foundations; it makes us label fashionable opinions as truth, instead of gauging their strength. Whereas science should be a free inquiry, it consists only in gibberish discussions on how we should read Aristotle or Galen. [ 9 ] Critical judgment is systematically silenced. Montaigne demands a thought process that would not be tied down by any doctrinaire principle, a thought process that would lead to free enquiry.

If we trace back the birth of modern science, we find that Montaigne as a philosopher was ahead of his time. In 1543, Copernicus put the earth in motion, depriving man of his cosmological centrality. Yet he nevertheless changed little in the medieval conception of the world as a sphere. The Copernican world became an “open” world only with Thomas Digges (1576) although his sky was still situated in space, inhabited by gods and angels. [ 10 ] One has to wait for Giordano Bruno to find the first representative of the modern conception of an infinite universe (1584). But whether Bruno is a modern mind remains controversial (the planets are still animals, etc). Montaigne, on the contrary, is entirely free from the medieval conception of the spheres. He owes his cosmological freedom to his deep interest in ancient philosophers, to Lucretius in particular. In the longest chapter of the Essays , the “Apologie de Raymond Sebond”, Montaigne conjures up many opinions, regarding the nature of the cosmos, or the nature of the soul. He weighs the Epicureans’ opinion that several worlds exist, against that of the unicity of the world put forth by both Aristotle and Aquinas. He comes out in favor of the former, without ranking his own evaluation as a truth.

As a humanist, Montaigne conceived of philosophy as morals. In the chapter “On the education of children”, [ 11 ] education is identified with philosophy, this being understood as the formation of judgment and manners in everyday life: “for philosophy, which, as the molder of judgment and conduct, will be his principal lesson, has the privilege of being everywhere at home”. [ 12 ] Philosophy, which consists essentially in the use of judgment, is significant to the very ordinary, varied and “undulating” [ 13 ] process of life. In fact, under the guise of innocuous anecdotes, Montaigne achieved the humanist revolution in philosophy. He moved from a conception of philosophy conceived of as theoretical science, to a philosophy conceived of as the practice of free judgment. Lamenting that “philosophy, even with people of understanding, should be an empty and fantastic name, a thing of no use and no value”, [ 14 ] he asserted that philosophy should be the most cheerful activity. He practised philosophy by setting his judgment to trial, in order to become aware of its weaknesses, but also to get to know its strength. “Every movement reveals us”, [ 15 ] but our judgments do so the best. At the beginning of the past century, one of Montaigne’s greatest commentators, Pierre Villey, developed the idea that Montaigne truly became himself through writing. This idea remains more or less true, in spite of its obvious link with late romanticist psychology. The Essays remain an exceptional historical testimony of the progress of privacy and individualism, a blossoming of subjectivity, an attainment of personal maturity that will be copied, but maybe never matched since. It seems that Montaigne, who dedicated himself to freedom of the mind and peacefulness of the soul, did not have any other aim through writing than cultivating and educating himself. Since philosophy had failed to determine a secure path towards happiness, he committed each individual to do so in his own way. [ 16 ]

Montaigne wants to escape the stifling of thought by knowledge, a wide-spread phenomenon which he called “pedantism”, [ 17 ] an idea that he may have gleaned from the tarnishing of professors by the Commedia dell’arte . He praises one of the most famous professors of the day, Adrianus Turnebus, for having combined robust judgment with massive erudition. We have to moderate our thirst for knowledge, just as we do our appetite for pleasure. Siding here with Callicles against Plato, Montaigne asserts that a gentleman should not dedicate himself entirely to philosophy. [ 18 ] Practised with restraint, it proves useful, whereas in excess it leads to eccentricity and insociability. [ 19 ] Reflecting on the education of the children of the aristocracy (chapter I, 26, is dedicated to the countess Diane de Foix, who was then pregnant), Montaigne departs significantly from a traditional humanist education, the very one he himself received. Instead of focusing on the ways and means of making the teaching of Latin more effective, as pedagogues in the wake of Erasmus usually did, Montaigne stresses the need for action and playful activities. The child will conform early to social and political customs, but without servility. The use of judgment in every circumstance, as a warrant for practical intelligence and personal freedom, has to remain at the core of education. He transfers the major responsibility of education from the school to everyday life: “Wonderful brilliance may be gained for human judgment by getting to know men”. [ 20 ] The priority given to the formation of judgment and character strongly opposes the craving for a powerful memory during his time. He reserves for himself the freedom to pick up bits of knowledge here and there, displaying the “nonchalance” or unconcern intellectually, much in the same way that Castiglione’s courtier would use sprezzatura in social relationships. Although Montaigne presents this nonchalance as essential to his nature, his position is not innocent: it allows him to take on the voice now of a Stoic, and then of a Sceptic, now of an Epicurean and then of a Christian. Although his views are never fully original, they always bear his unmistakable mark. Montaigne’s thought, which is often rated as modern in so many aspects, remains deeply rooted in the classical tradition. Montaigne navigates easily through heaps of classical knowledge, proposing remarkable literary and philosophical innovations along the way.

Montaigne begins his project to know man by noticing that the same human behavior can have opposite effects, or that even opposite conducts can have the same effects: “by diverse means we arrive at the same end”. [ 21 ] Human life cannot be turned into an object of rational theory. Human conduct does not obey universal rules, but a great diversity of rules, among which the most accurate still fall short of the intended mark. “Human reason is a tincture infused in about equal strength in all our opinions and ways, whatever their form: infinite in substance, infinite in diversity” [ 22 ] says the chapter on custom. By focusing on anecdotal experience, Montaigne comes thus to write “the masterpiece of modern moral science”, according to the great commentator Hugo Friedrich. He gives up the moral ambition of telling how men should live, in order to arrive at a non-prejudiced mind for knowing man as he is. “Others form man, I tell of him”. [ 23 ] Man is ever since “without a definition”, as philosopher Marcel Conche commented. [ 24 ] In the chapter “Apologie de Raimond Sebond”, Montaigne draws from classical and Renaissance knowledge in order to remind us that, in some parts of the world, we find men that bear little resemblance to us. Our experience of man and things should not be perceived as limited by our present standards of judgment. It is a sort of madness when we settle limits for the possible and the impossible. [ 25 ]

Philosophy has failed to secure man a determined idea of his place in the world, or of his nature. Metaphysical or psychological opinions, indeed far too numerous, come as a burden more than as a help. Montaigne pursues his quest for knowledge through experience; the meaning of concepts is not set down by means of a definition, it is related to common language or to historical examples. One of the essential elements of experience is the ability to reflect on one’s actions and thoughts. Montaigne is engaging in a case-by-case gnôti seauton , “know thyself”: although truth in general is not truly an appropriate object for human faculties, we can reflect on our experience. What counts is not the fact that we eventually know the truth or not, but rather the way in which we seek it. “The question is not who will hit the ring, but who will make the best runs at it.” [ 26 ] The aim is to properly exercise our judgment.

Montaigne’s thinking baffles our most common categories. The vision of an ever-changing world that he developed threatens the being of all things. “We have no communication with being”. [ 27 ] We wrongly take that which appears for that which is, and we indulge in a dogmatic, deceptive language that is cut off from an ever-changing reality. We ought to be more careful with our use of language. Montaigne would prefer that children be taught other ways of speaking, more appropriate to the nature of human inquiry, such as “What does that mean ?”, “I do not understand it”, “This might be”, “Is it true?” [ 28 ] Montaigne himself is fond of “these formulas that soften the boldness of our propositions”: “perhaps”, “to some extent”, “they say”, “I think”, [ 29 ] and the like. Criticism on theory and dogmatism permeates for example his reflexion on politics. Because social order is too complicated to be mastered by individual reason, he deems conservatism as the wisest stance. [ 30 ] This policy is grounded on the general evaluation that change is usually more damaging than the conservation of social institutions. Nevertheless, there may be certain circumstances that advocate change as a better solution, as history sometimes showed. Reason being then unable to decide a priori , judgment must come into play and alternate its views to find the best option.

With Cornelius Agrippa, Henri Estienne or Francisco Sanchez, among others, Montaigne has largely contributed to the rebirth of scepticism during the XVI th century. His literary encounter with Sextus produced a decisive shock: around 1576, when Montaigne had his own personal medal coined, he had it engraved with his age, with “ Epecho ” , “I abstain” in Greek, and another Sceptic motto in French: “ Que sais-je ?”: what do I know ? At this period in his life, Montaigne is thought to have undergone a “sceptical crisis”, as Pierre Villey famously commented. In fact, this interpretation dates back to Pascal, for whom scepticism could only be a sort of momentary frenzy. [ 31 ] The “Apologie de Raimond Sebond”, the longest chapter of the Essays , bears the sign of intellectual despair that Montaigne manages to shake off elsewhere. But another interpretation of scepticism formulates it as a strategy used to confront “fideism”: because reason is unable to demonstrate religious dogmas, we must rely on spiritual revelation and faith. The paradigm of fideism, a word which Montaigne does not use, has been delivered by Richard Popkin in History of Scepticism [ 32 ] . Montaigne appears here as a founding father of the Counter Reformation, being the leader of the “Nouveaux Pyrrhoniens”, for whom scepticism is used as a means to an end, that is, to neutralize the grip that philosophy once had on religion.

Commentators now agree upon the fact that Montaigne largely transformed the type of scepticism he borrowed from Sextus. The two sides of the scale are never perfectly balanced, since reason always tips the scale in favor of the present at hand. This imbalance undermines the key mechanism of isosthenia , the equality of strength of two opposing arguments. Since the suspension of judgment cannot occur “casually”, as Sextus Empiricus would like it to, judgment must abstain from giving its assent. In fact, the sources of Montaigne’s scepticism are much wider: his child readings of Ovid’s Metamorphosis , which gave him a deep awareness of change, the in utramque partem academic debate which he practised at the Collège de Guyenne (a pro and contra discussion inherited from Aristotle and Cicero), and the humanist philosophy of action, dealing with the uncertainty of human affairs, shaped his mind early on. Through them, he learned repeatedly that rational appearances are deceptive. In most of the chapters of the Essays , Montaigne now and then reverses his judgment: these sudden shifts of perspective are designed to escape adherence, and to tackle the matter from another point of view. [ 33 ] The Essays mirror a discreet conduct of judgment, in keeping with the formula iudicio alternante , which we still find engraved today on the beams of the Périgord castle’s library. The aim is not to ruin arguments by opposing them, as it is the case in the Pyrrhonian “antilogy”, but rather to counterbalance a single opinion by taking into account other opinions. In order to work, each scale of judgment has to be laden. If we take morals, for example, Montaigne refers to varied moral authorities, one of them being custom and the other reason. Against every form of dogmatism, Montaigne returns moral life to its original diversity and inherent uneasiness. Through philosophy, he seeks full accordance with the diversity of life: “As for me, I love life and cultivate it as God has been pleased to grant it to us”. [ 34 ]

We find two readings of Montaigne as a Sceptic. The first one concentrates on the polemical, negative arguments drawn from Sextus Empiricus, at the end of the “Apology”. This hard-line scepticism draws the picture of man as “humiliated”. [ 35 ] Its aim is essentially to fight the pretensions of reason and to annihilate human knowledge. “Truth”, “being” and “justice” are equally dismissed as unattainable. Doubt foreshadows here Descartes’ Meditations , on the problem of the reality of the outside world. Dismissing the objective value of one’s representations, Montaigne would have created the long-lasting problem of “solipsism”. We notice, nevertheless, that he does not question the reality of things — except occasionally at the very end of the “Apology” — but the value of opinions and men. The second reading of his scepticism puts forth that Cicero’s probabilism is of far greater significance in shaping the sceptical content of the Essays . After the 1570s, Montaigne no longer read Sextus; additions show, however, that he took up a more and more extensive reading of Cicero’s philosophical writings. We assume that, in his early search for polemical arguments against rationalism during the 1570s, Montaigne borrowed much from Sextus, but as he got tired of the sceptical machinery, and understood scepticism rather as an ethics of judgment, he went back to Cicero. [ 36 ] The paramount importance of the Academica for XVI th century thought has been underlined by Charles B. Schmitt. [ 37 ] In the free enquiry, which Cicero engaged throughout the varied doctrines, the humanists found an ideal mirror of their own relationship with the Classics. “The Academy, of which I am a follower, gives me the opportunity to hold an opinion as if it were ours, as soon as it shows itself to be highly probable” [ 38 ] , wrote Cicero in the De Officiis . Reading Seneca, Montaigne will think as if he were a member of the Stoa; then changing for Lucretius, he will think as if he had become an Epicurean, and so on. Doctrines or opinions, beside historical stuff and personal experiences, make up the nourishment of judgment. Montaigne assimilates opinions, according to what appears to him as true, without taking it to be absolutely true. He insists on the dialogical nature of thought, referring to Socrates’ way of keeping the discussion going: “The leader of Plato’s dialogues, Socrates, is always asking questions and stirring up discussion, never concluding, never satisfying (…).” [ 39 ] Judgment has to determine the most convincing position, or at least to determine the strengths and weaknesses of each position. The simple dismissal of truth would be too dogmatic a position; but if absolute truth is lacking, we still have the possibility to balance opinions. We have resources enough, to evaluate the various authorities that we have to deal with in ordinary life.

The original failure of commentators was perhaps in labelling Montaigne’s thought as “sceptic” without reflecting on the proper meaning of the essay. Montaigne’s exercise of judgment is an exercise of “natural judgment”, which means that judgment does not need any principle or any rule as a presupposition. In this way, many aspects of Montaigne’s thinking can be considered as sceptical, although they were not used for the sake of scepticism. For example, when Montaigne sets down the exercise of doubt as a good start in education, he understands doubt as part of the process of the formation of judgment. This process should lead to wisdom, characterized as “always joyful”. [ 40 ] Montaigne’s scepticism is not a desperate one. On the contrary, it offers the reader a sort of jubilation which relies on the modest but effective pleasure in dismissing knowledge, thus making room for the exercise of one’s natural faculties.

Renaissance thinkers strongly felt the necessity to revise their discourse on man. But no one accentuated this necessity more than Montaigne: what he was looking for, when reading historians or travellers such as Lopez de Gomara’s History of Indies , was the utmost variety of beliefs and customs that would enrich his image of man. Neither the Hellenistic Sage, nor the Christian Saint, nor the Renaissance Scholar, are unquestioned models in the Essays . Instead, Montaigne is considering real men, who are the product of customs. “Here they live on human flesh; there it is an act of piety to kill one’s father at a certain age (…).” [ 41 ] The importance of custom plays a polemical part: alongside with scepticism, the strength of imagination (chapter I,21) or Fortune (chapters I,1, I,24, etc.), it contributes to the devaluation of reason and will. It is bound to destroy our spontaneous confidence that we do know the truth, and that we live according to justice. During the XVI th century, the jurists of the “French school of law” showed that the law is tied up with historical determinations. [ 42 ] In chapter I,23, “On custom”, Montaigne seems to extrapolate on this idea : our opinions and conducts being everywhere the product of custom, references to universal “reason”, “truth”, or “justice” are to be dismissed as illusions. Pierre Villey was the first to use the terms “relativity” and “relativism”, which proved to be useful tools when commenting on the fact that Montaigne acknowledges that no universal reason presides over the birth of our beliefs. [ 43 ] The notion of absolute truth, applied to human matters, vitiates the understanding and wreaks havoc in society. Upon further reflexion, contingent customs impact everything: “in short, to my way of thinking, there is nothing that custom will not or cannot do”. [ 44 ] Montaigne calls it “Circe’s drink”. [ 45 ] Custom is a sort of witch, whose spell, among other effects, casts moral illusion. “The laws of conscience, which we say are born from nature, are born of custom. Each man, holding in inward veneration the opinions and the behavior approved and accepted around him, cannot break loose from them without remorse, or apply himself to them without self-satisfaction.” [ 46 ] The power of custom, indeed, not only guides man in his behavior, but also persuades him of its legitimacy. What is crime for one person will appear normal to another. In the XVII th century, Blaise Pascal will use this argument when challenging the pretension of philosophers of knowing truth. One century later, David Hume will lay stress on the fact that the power of custom is all the stronger, specifically because we are not aware of it. What are we supposed to do, then, if our reason is so flexible that it “changes with two degrees of elevation towards the pole”, as Pascal puts it? [ 47 ] For the Jansenist thinker, only one alternative exists, faith in Jesus Christ. However, it is more complicated in the case of Montaigne. Getting to know all sorts of customs, through his readings or travels, he makes an exemplary effort to open his mind. “We are all huddled and concentrated in ourselves, and our vision is reduced to the length of our nose.” [ 48 ] Custom’s grip is so strong that it is dubious as to whether we are in a position to become aware of it and shake off its power.

Montaigne was hailed by Claude Lévi-Strauss as the progenitor of the human sciences, and the pioneer of cultural relativism. [ 49 ] However, Montaigne has not been willing to indulge entirely in relativism. Judgment is at first sight unable to stop the relativistic discourse, but it is not left without remedy when facing the power of custom. Exercise of thought is the first counterweight we can make use of, for example when criticizing an existing law. Customs are not almighty, since their authority can be reflected upon, evaluated or challenged by individual judgment. The comparative method can also be applied to the freeing of judgment: although lacking a universal standard, we can nevertheless stand back from particular customs, by the mere fact of comparing them. Montaigne thus compares heating or circulating means between people. In a more tragical way, he denounces the fanaticism and the cruelty displayed by Christians against one another, during the civil wars in France, through a comparison with cannibalism: “I think there is more barbarity in eating a man alive than in eating him dead, and in tearing by tortures and the rack a body still full of feeling (…).” [ 50 ] The meaning of the word “barbarity” is not merely relative to a culture or a point of view, since there are degrees of barbarity. Passing a judgment on cannibals, Montaigne also says: “So we may well call these people barbarians, in respect to the rules of reason, but not in respect to ourselves, who surpass them in every kind of barbarity (…).” [ 51 ] Judgment is still endowed with the possibility of postulating universal standards, such as “reason” or “nature”, which help when evaluating actions and behaviors. Although Montaigne maintains in the “Apologie” that true reason and true justice are only known by God, he asserts in other chapters that these standards are somehow accessible to man, since they allow judgment to consider customs as particular and contingent rules. [ 52 ] In order to criticize the changeable and the relative, we must suppose that our judgment is still able to “bring things back to truth and reason”. [ 53 ] Man is everywhere enslaved by custom, but this does not mean that we should accept the numbing of our mind. Montaigne elaborates a pedagogy, which rests on the practice of judgment itself. The task of the pupil is not to repeat what the master said, but, on a given subject of problem, to confront his judgment with the master’s one. Moreover, relativistic readings of the Essays are forced to ignore certain passages that carry a more rationalistic tone. “The violent detriment inflicted by custom” (I,23) is certainly not a praise of custom, but an invitation to escape it. In the same way that Circe’s potion has changed men into pigs, custom turns their intelligence into stupidity. In the toughest cases, Montaigne’s critical use of judgment aims at giving “a good whiplash to the ordinary stupidity of judgment.” [ 54 ] In many other places, Montaigne boasts of himself being able to resist vulgar opinion. Independence of thinking, alongside with clear-mindedness and good faith, are the first virtues a young gentleman should acquire.

Pierre Charron was Montaigne’s friend and official heir. In De la sagesse (1601 and 1604), he re-organized many of his master’s ideas, setting aside the most disturbing ones. His work is now usually dismissed as a dogmatic misrepresentation of Montaigne’s thought. Nevertheless, his book was given priority over the Essays themselves during the whole XVII th century, especially after Malebranche’s critics conspired to have the Essays included in the Roman Index of 1677. Montaigne’s historical influence must be reckoned through the lens of this mediation. Moreover, Charron’s reading is not simply faulty. According to him, wisdom relies on the readiness of judgment to revise itself towards a more favorable outcome: [ 55 ] this idea is one of the most remarkable readings of the Essays in the early history of their reception.

The critical conception of the essay was taken up by the English scientist and philosopher Francis Bacon, who considered his own Essays as “fragments of [his] conceits” and “dispersed meditations”, aiming to stimulate the reader’s appetite for thinking and knowledge rather than satisfying it with expositions of dogmas and methods. [ 56 ] Even in his more scientific works, such as The Advancement of Learning , Bacon’s writing was inconclusive. He posited that this open and fragmentary style was the best way to inspire further thought and examination: “Aphorisms, representing a knowledge broken, do invite men to inquire further”. [ 57 ] Bacon’s reflections allow us to appreciate the scientific value of Montaigne’s Essays, insofar as they are incomplete works, always calling for subsequent reflections by the author and the reader, thus inspiring and promoting the development of ideas and the advancement of research.

The influence Montaigne had on Descartes has been commented upon by many critics, at least from the XIX th century on, within the context of the birth of modern science. As a sceptic, calling into question the natural link between mind and things, Montaigne would have won his position in the modern philosophical landscape. The scepticism in the “Apologie” is, no doubt, a main source of “solipsism”, but Descartes cannot be called a disciple of Montaigne in the sense that he would have inherited a doctrine. Above all, he owes the Périgourdin gentleman a way of educating himself. Far from substituting Montaigne for his Jesuit schoolteachers, Descartes decided to teach himself from scratch, following the path indicated by Montaigne to achieve independence and firmness of judgment. The mindset that Descartes inherited from the Essays appears as something particularly obvious, in the two first parts of the Discours de la méthode . As the young Descartes left the Collège de La Flèche, he decided to travel, and to test his own value in action. “I employed the rest of my youth to travel, to see courts and armies, to meet people of varied humors and conditions, to collect varied experiences, to try myself in the meetings that fortune was offering me (…).” [ 58 ] Education, taken out of a school context, is presented as an essay of the self through experience. The world, as pedagogue, has been substituted for books and teachers. This new education allows Descartes to get rid of the prejudice of overrating his own customs, a widespread phenomenon that we now call ethnocentrism. Montaigne’s legacy becomes particularly conspicuous when Descartes draws the lesson from his travels, “having acknowledged that those who have very contrary feelings to ours are not barbarians or savages, but that many of them make use of reason as much or more so than we do”. And also : “It is good to know something of different people, in order to judge our own with more sanity, and not to think that everything that is against our customs and habits is ridiculous and against reason, as usually do those who have never seen anything.” [ 59 ] Like Montaigne, Descartes begins by philosophizing on life with no other device than the a discipline of judgment: “I was learning not to believe anything too firmly, of which I had been persuaded through example and custom.” [ 60 ] He departs nevertheless from Montaigne when he will equate with error opinions that are grounded on custom. [ 61 ] The latter would not have dared to speak of error: varied opinions, having more or less authority, are to be weighed upon the scale of judgment. It is thus not correct to interpret Montaigne’s philosophy as a “criticism of prejudice” from a Cartesian stance.

In recent years, critics have stressed the importance of the connection between Montaigne and Hobbes for the development of a modern vision of politics, rooted in a criticism of traditional doctrines of man and society. At the time when Shakespeare was writing his plays, the first English translation of Montaigne’s Essays by John Florio (1603) became a widely-read classic in England. As a former student of Magdalen Hall (Oxford) and Saint John’s College (Cambridge), and as a young tutor and secretary to aristocratic and wealthy families, Thomas Hobbes had many opportunities to read Montaigne in the libraries he frequented. In his capacity as tutor, he traveled widely in Europe and spent several sojourns in France, before the English Civil War forced him into exile in Paris (1641–1651). During this period, Hobbes moved in skeptical and libertine circles and met scholars such as Sorbière, Gassendi, and La Mothe Le Vayer, all influenced by a shared reference to Montaigne’s skepticism. Historical documents and comparative research confirm the relevance of Montaigne’s influence on Hobbes’s work, from Elements of Law to Leviathan . [ 62 ] The two authors share a philosophical conception of man as driven by desire and imagination, and relentlessly striving for self-conservation and power. Montaigne identified human life with movement and instability, and pointed to the power that our passions have to push us toward imaginary future accomplishments (honor, glory, science, reason, and so on). [ 63 ] In Leviathan , Hobbes builds on this position to assert, as a general inclination of all mankind, “a perpetual and restless desire of power after power, that ceases only in death”. [ 64 ] This shared anthropology shows the extent to which Montaigne and Hobbes refute the Scholastic and Renaissance anthropocentric idea of man as a rational being at the summit of creation. On the contrary, they underline his instinctive and passionate nature, which eventually leads to violence and conflict wherever the political community collapses. This negative anthropology is to be understood in the light of the historical experience of the civil wars upsetting both their countries. [ 65 ] The threat of political turmoil imbued both Montaigne and Hobbes’ lives. Whereas Hobbes quoted the ancient saying homo homini lupus , and described the human condition outside the civil state as a war “where every man is enemy to every man”, [ 66 ] Montaigne seemed to go further, “having learned by experience, from the cruelty of some Christians, that there is no beast in the world to be feared by man as man”. [ 67 ] In order to avoid the outburst of violence, they both recognize the necessity of laws and obedience, a necessity that does not rely on any ontological or moral foundation. The normative force of law results from its practical necessity, as it is the rational condition of life in society. [ 68 ] As Montaigne wrote: “Now laws remain in credit not because they are just, but because they are laws”. [ 69 ] Questioning the Aristotelian vision of politics as a natural goal for humanity, Montaigne and Hobbes pointed out the man-made nature of civil authority, as founded in the need to preserve life and peace, avoiding violence and war.

Montaigne cultivates his liberty by not adhering exclusively to any one idea, while at the same time exploring them all. In exercising his judgment on various topics, he trains himself to go off on fresh tracks, starting from something he read or experienced. For Montaigne this also means calling into question the convictions of his time, reflecting upon his beliefs and education, and cultivating his own personal thoughts. His language can be said to obey only one rule, that is, to be “an effect of judgment and sincerity,” [ 70 ] which is the very one that he demands from the pupil. His language bears an unmistakable tone but contradicts itself sometimes from one place to another, perhaps for the very reason that it follows so closely the movements of thought.

If being a philosopher means being insensitive to human frailties and to the evils or to the pleasures which befall us, then Montaigne is not a philosopher. If it means using a “jargon”, and being able to enter the world of scholars, then Montaigne is not one either. Yet, if being a philosopher is being able to judge properly in any circumstances of life, then the Essays are the exemplary testimony of an author who wanted to be a philosopher for good. Montaigne is putting his judgment to trial on whatever subject, in order not only to get to know its value, but also to form and strengthen it.

He manages thus to offer us a philosophy in accordance with life. As Nietzsche puts it, “that such a man has written, joy on earth has truly increased…If my task were to make this earth a home, I would attach myself to him.” Or, as Stefan Zweig said, in a context which was closer to the historical reality experienced by Montaigne himself : “Montaigne helps us answer this one question: ‘How to stay free? How to preserve our inborn clear-mindedness in front of all the threats and dangers of fanaticism, how to preserve the humanity of our hearts among the upsurge of bestiality?’”

  • Essais , F. Strowski (ed.), Paris: Hachette, 1912, Phototypic reproduction of the “Exemplaire de Bordeaux”, showing Montaigne’s handwritten additions of 1588–1592.
  • Essais , Pierre Villey (ed.), 3 volumes, Alcan, 1922–1923, revised by V.-L. Saulnier, 1965. Gives the 3 strata indications, probable dates of composition of the chapters, and many sources.
  • Michel de Montaigne. Les Essais , J. Balsamo, C. Magnien-Simonin & M. Magnien (eds.) (with “Notes de lecture” and “Sentences peintes” edited by Alain Legros), Paris, “Pléiade”, Gallimard, 2007. The Essays are based on the 1595 published version.
  • La Théologie naturelle de Raymond Sebond , traduicte nouvellement en François par Messire Michel, Seigneur de Montaigne, Chevalier de l’ordre du Roy et Gentilhomme ordinaire de sa chambre . Ed. by Dr Armaingaud, Paris: Conard, 1935.
  • Le Journal de Voyage en Italie de Michel de Montaigne . Ed. by François Rigolot, Paris: PUF, 1992.
  • Lettres . Ed. by Arthur Armaingaud, Paris, Conard, 1939 (vol. XI, in Œuvres complètes , pp. 159–266).
  • The Essayes , tr. by John Florio. London: V. Sims, 1603.
  • The Essays , tr. by Charles Cotton. 3 vol., London: T. Basset, M. Gilliflower and W. Hensman, 1685–1686.
  • The Essays , tr. by E.J. Trechmann. 2 vol., Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1927.
  • Michel de Montaigne. The Complete Works. Essays, Travel Journal, Letters, tr. by Donald M. Frame , Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1958, renewed 1971 & 1976.
  • The Complete Essays , tr. by M.A. Screech, London/New York: Penguin, 1993.
  • The Journal of Montaigne’s Travels , tr. by W.G. Watters, 3 vol., London: John Murray, 1903.
  • The Diary of Montaigne’s Journey to Italy in 1580 and 1581 , tr. by E.J. Trechmann. London: Hogarth Press, 1929.
  • Auerbach, Erich, 1946, “l’humaine condition” (on Montaigne) in Mimesis: The Representation of Reality in Western Literature, trans . Willard Trask. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2003 (originally pub. Bern: Francke).
  • Burke, Peter, 1981, Montaigne , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Compayré, Gabriel, 1908, Montaigne and the Education of the Judgment, trans. J. E. Mansion, New York: Burt Franklin, 1971.
  • Conche, Marcel, 1996, Montaigne et la philosophie , Paris: PUF.
  • Desan, Philippe, 2017, Montaigne: A Life , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • ––– (ed.), 2007, Dictionnaire de Montaigne , Paris: Champion.
  • ––– (ed.), 2016, The Oxford Handbook of Montaigne , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ferrari, Emiliano, & Gontier, Thierry, 2016, L’Axe Montaigne-Hobbes: anthropologie et politique , Paris: Classiques Garnier.
  • Frame, Donald M., 1984, Montaigne: A Biography , New York: Harcourt/ London: Hamish Hamilton, 1965/ San Francisco: North Point Press.
  • Friedrich, Hugo, 1991, Montaigne , Bern: Francke, 1949; Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Fontana, Biancamaria, 2008, Montaigne’s Politics: Authority and Governance in the Essays , Geneva: Princeton University Press.
  • Hoffmann, Georges, 1998, Montaigne’s Career , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Horkheimer, Max, 1938, Montaigne und die Funktion der Skepsis , Frankfurt: Fischer, reprinted 1971.
  • Imbach, Ruedi, 1983, “‘Et toutefois nostre outrecuidance veut faire passer la divinité par nostre estamine’, l’essai II,12 et la genèse de la pensée moderne. Construction d’une thèse explicative” in Paradigmes de théologie philosophique , O. Höffe et R. Imbach (eds.), Fribourg.
  • Ulrich Langer, 2005, The Cambridge Companion to Montaigne , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Leake, R.E., 1981, Concordance des Essais de Montaigne , 2 vol., Genève: Droz.
  • Paganini, Gianni, 2008, Skepsis. Le débat des modernes sur le scepticisme , Paris: Vrin.
  • Popkin, Richard, 1960, The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Descartes , Assen: Van Gorcum.
  • –––, 1979, The History of Scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza , Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • –––, 2003, The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Schmitt, Charles B., 1972, Cicero scepticus : A Study of the Influence of the Academica in the Renaissance , The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
  • Screech, Michael, 1983, Montaigne & Melancholy — The Wisdom of the Essays , London: Duckworth.
  • –––, 1998, Montaigne’s Annotated Copy of Lucretius, A transcription and study of the manuscript, notes and pen-marks , Geneva: Droz.
  • Skinner, Quentin, 2002, Visions of Politics (Volume 3: Hobbes and Civil Science), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Starobinski, Jean, 2009, Montaigne in Motion , University of Chicago Press.
  • Supple, James, 1984, Arms versus Letters, The Military and Literary Ideals in the Essays , Cambridge: Clarendon Press.
  • Thompson, Douglas, 2018, Montaigne and the Tolerance of Politics , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Tournon, André, 1983, La glose et l’essai , Paris: H. Champion, reprinted 2001.
  • Zweig, Stefan, 1960, Montaigne [written 1935–1941] Frankfurt: Fischer.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources

  • The complete, searchable text of the Villey-Saulnier edition , from the ARFTL project at the University of Chicago (French)
  • Montaigne Studies: An Interdisciplinary Forum , Philippe Desan, ed., (University of Chicago).
  • Portrait Gallery , in Montaigne Studies: An Interdisciplinary Forum
  • Montaigne’s Essays John Florio’s translation (first published 1603, Ben R. Schneider (ed.), Lawrence University, Wisconsin, from The World’s Classics, 1904, 1910, 1924), published at Renascence Editions, U. Oregon
  • Essays of Michel De Montaigne , translated (1685–1686) by Charles Cotton, edited by William Carew Hazlitt, London: Reeves anbd Turner.

civic humanism | Descartes, René | -->humanism: in the Renaissance --> | liberty: positive and negative | relativism | Sextus Empiricus | skepticism | Stoicism

Copyright © 2019 by Marc Foglia < marc . foglia @ gmail . com > Emiliano Ferrari < ferrariemil @ gmail . com >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

BrightSummaries.com – Literature in a new light

Essays by Michel de Montaigne (Book Analysis)

Detailed summary, analysis and reading guide.

This practical and insightful  reading guide  offers a  complete summary  and  analysis  of the  Essays,  by  Michel de Montaigne . It provides a thorough exploration of the essay’s plot, context and main themes, including – to list but a few – medicine, knowledge and manners. The clear and concise style makes for easy understanding, providing the perfect opportunity to improve your literary knowledge in no time.

This clear and detailed 50-page reading guide is structured as follows:

  • Biography of Michel de Montaigne
  • Presentation of the  Essays
  • Summary of the  Essays
  • The composition and structure of the Essays
  • A self-portrait
  • Montaigne’s writing
  • A critical judgement
  • Human relationships
  • The search for wisdom

About the  Essays

The Essays  were first published in 1580 after ten years of writing. They deal with a huge variety of themes and subjects, including – but not limited to – medicine, knowledge, manners and reflections on life in general. In addressing such a wide range of questions, Montaigne hoped to discover the reality of the human condition. In the work, Montaigne paints himself as he truly is, so that his loved ones can find solace in his Essays after his death.

About Michel de Montaigne

Michel Eyquem de Montaigne, Lord of Montaigne, was a French writer, philosopher, politician and humanist during the Renaissance. He was born in 1533. He was a great traveler, particularly for his time – he journeyed through France, Switzerland, South Germany and Italy, to name but a few of the places he visited, and wrote about this time in his Journal de voyage en Italie .

Montaigne was also very involved in French politics; he even became the mayor of Bordeaux later on in his life. However, reading and writing were his passion and came before all other occupations, which is what led to his famous  Essays . He had a major work on many Western writers, including Jean-Jacques Rousseau and – possibly – William Shakespeare.

Product details

  • Share On Facebook
  • Tweet This Product
  • Pin This Product
  • Mail This Product

Related guides

The School for Wives by Molière (Book Analysis)

The School for Wives by Molière (Book Analysis)

Bel Ami by Guy de Maupassant (Book Analysis)

Bel Ami by Guy de Maupassant (Book Analysis)

Art by Yasmina Reza (Book Analysis)

Art by Yasmina Reza (Book Analysis)

Dom Juan by Molière (Book Analysis)

Dom Juan by Molière (Book Analysis)

No Exit by Jean-Paul Sartre (Book Analysis)

No Exit by Jean-Paul Sartre (Book Analysis)

Antigone by Jean Anouilh (Book Analysis)

Antigone by Jean Anouilh (Book Analysis)

Already subscribed ? Click here

Find the right plan for you

Brightsummaries standard.

  • Ideal for casual readers
  • More than 200 guides
  • Download 5 guides per month
  • Standard technical support

BrightSummaries Premium

  • Ideal for serious readers
  • Download 20 guides per month
  • Premium technical support
  • Project Gutenberg
  • 73,222 free eBooks
  • 33 by Michel de Montaigne

Essays of Michel de Montaigne — Volume 11 by Michel de Montaigne

Book Cover

Of Cannibals | Summary and Analysis

Summary of michel de montaigne's of cannibals.

Michel de Montaigne was a renowned 16th-century French philosopher who popularized essay writing as a literary genre and wrote intellectual and thought-provoking essays on human existence and the truths of life. “Of Cannibals” is one of the essays from his 1580 collection of the same name that exposes Europe’s preoccupation with dualities by centering themselves as a model for the whole world. What Europeans think of barbarians and why they ascribe savagery to non-Europeans form the basis of this work. Montaigne analyses the lifestyle of barbarians i.e. the inhabitants of Brazil to create a discourse on knowledge and humanity’s capacity to inflict as well as bear cruelty. 

Of Cannibals | Summary

The essay begins with Montaigne stating the “vulgar opinion” that Europeans have built about the non-Europeans as barbaric creatures by drawing on King Pyrrhus’ statement on the Roman army. Greeks’ belief of savagery prevailing in everyone who does not belong to their nationality is undermined when the king is impressed with the Roman army’s disciplinary welcome and disbelieves them to be barbaric. Montaigne insists on deploying reason and personal experience while forming an opinion. Similarly, Europeans during their expedition into South America came across Brazilians whom they considered barbaric because of their inhabitance of wild lands. However, Montaigne offers an alternate view of their life which is somewhat utopic and catalogs various customs and practices that stand in complete contrast to Europe’s. He draws on Plato’s story of Atlantis as the great island that faces the repercussions of a flood in its quest for expansion.

Montaigne further converses with a man whose life in the New World for a couple of years becomes a diary of life experiences without any filters as he is a plain man. Montaigne emphasizes the need to stop believing in the commonly held notions and rather believe in what you see or hear personally by employing the faculty of Reason. 

Just like the Greeks’ opinion on Romans, Europeans think of Brazilians, and all non-Europeans for that matter as savages. But Montaigne says that their conditions of life are devoid of manipulation and poverty with equality prevailing and proximity to nature. They do not dispute over territories; have no concepts of finance, deceit, corruption, or any other vices except bloodshed and war which is equivalent to honor, glory, and valor. The will to surrender undermines the physical endurance of a captive. Physical submission is nothing until their will also submits. Montaigne realizes the barbaric tendencies in their treatment towards the prisoners who they cut into pieces and eat amongst themselves. There is no employment but only leisure activities where wives prepare drinks for the men and as a polygamous community, would often seek out other wives for their husbands because it would contribute to their husband’s grandiosity and stature. Religion operates outside their life and does not mediate in their daily activities.

With all this said Montaigne ventures to draw similarities as well as differences between Europeans and the citizens of the New World and concludes them to be not different from each other. Europe’s obsession with its own image blinds it to see faults in its own customs and civilization. For the so-called barbarians, humanity is one as they address the people in Europe as halves. They are astonished to see Europe having poor vagabonds suffering and begging when rich people are comfortable sleeping in their houses. 

Of Cannibals | Analysis

Montaigne’s subtle critique of Europe’s perception of colonies’ barbaric and savage lifestyle is a literary masterpiece that compels all the readers to contemplate their own belief system as well as to scrutinize their opinion formation solely on the basis of hearsay. He wrote the essay during the era when Europe was battling with corruption and violence as a consequence of wars and conquests all over the world. He tempts the readers through his “discursive tossing” by implicitly exposing the latent hypocrisy in Europe’s conduct and mannerisms.

The essay is premised on the French expedition to South America in 1557 and subsequent accounts that delineated a meticulous description of the Brazilians who he admired for living in an idealistic setting but popularly became a victim of contempt for their cannibalism. Montaigne thus willingly bears the onus of critically commenting on the Brazilians’ way of living and determining the credibility of the said notions. He employs analogy and allusion especially to noble European philosophers as the key rhetorical strategies to accelerate his arguments with precision. 

Of Cannibals | Key Arguments

The foremost observation Montaigne expresses is about the herd mentality people often engage in. One should always believe in what he/she sees rather than what he/she hears from others, like King Pyrrhus who casted his own take on the Romans as not barbaric but rather disciplined and mannered. Montaigne states- “we are to judge by the eye of reason, and not from the common report” and establishes the basis of his thought-provoking work. 

Often when a new land is discovered, its essence is lost in the worldly hunger of absorbing what is naked to the eye. Explorers in their travelogues attempt to amass everything they see and their empirical accounts over the years formulate into theories that are biased and incomplete in a sense as Montaigne asserts that “our eyes are bigger than our bellies, and that we have more curiosity than capacity; for we grasp at all, but catch nothing but wind.” The prosperity of discourse and literature on the communities settled in different parts of the world is an outcome of the glossing and altering of the stories by the “better-bred sort of men” like in the flourishing of an oriental discourse on the orients in the succeeding centuries. Things are presented as what they appear and mean to those men instead of what they actually are. 

Art has gained preeminence over its subject i.e. nature and this in Montaigne’s opinion is itself barbarism for we have made additions to its existing beauty through our own inventions which is equivalent to smothering her. The few remote areas which have managed to escape such victimization tend to appear primitive and savage to us for they don’t suit our vanity. Barbarism hence is nothing but any foreign practice that is alien to us, that we are not accustomed to. 

Calling out to Plato and other great historical and literary icons, he articulates satirically about their lack of belief in a:

“human society [which] could have been maintained with so little artifice and human patchwork.”

To further substantiate his stand, Montaigne enlists the various features of the New World, near to perfection yet incomprehensible to a man residing in the “lying, treachery, dissimulation, avarice, envy [and] detraction” operated environment. 

Ahead in the essay, he draws a comparison between the Europeans and the Brazilians concluding the former to be barbaric too. Their exotic and ‘othered’ status in the penmanship of various travelers is expelled by Montaigne who allows their assimilation into civilization just like the rest of the world. Indigenousness and proximity to nature had always kept them at bay in the Eurocentric world but primitivism has rather enabled them to be free of corrupting influences of the world. The people of Brazil live harmoniously with no power conflicts amongst themselves due to the expansion of land, which Europe was, and to some extent, even today is notoriously famous for. The women of the New World also follow the dictates of domesticity and gender hierarchy as Europe’s women do in their subservience to their husbands. They even believe in the immortality of the soul- a philosophy proposed by Plato thus connecting them with the European thought process. 

However, there is some incivility to their conduct too when they do not hesitate to rip their priest into thousand pieces for his false divination. Viewing it from two perspectives, the sheer brutality involving the act deems them closer to savagery but the driving force i.e. to punish falsity is an ethical justification for the act. Church and thus religion has always dominated European nations and has in effect become the impetus for the colonial enterprise.  

War too is a bloody phenomenon in their culture where they only fight with nations within the mainland and beyond the mountains:

“Everyone for a trophy brings home the head of an enemy he has killed, which he fixes over the door of his house. After having a long time treated their prisoners very well, and given them all the regales they can think of, he to whom the prisoner belongs, invites a great assembly of his friends. They being come, he ties a rope to one of the arms of the prisoner, of which, at a distance, out of his reach, he holds the one end himself, and gives to the friend he loves best the other arm to hold after the same manner; which being. done, they two, in the presence of all the assembly, dispatch him with their swords. After that, they roast him, eat him amongst them, and send some chops to their absent friends. They do not do this, as some think, for nourishment, as the Scythians anciently did, but as a representation of extreme revenge; as will appear by this: that having observed the Portuguese, who were in league with their enemies, to inflict another sort of death upon any of them they took prisoners, which was to set them up to the girdle in the earth, to shoot at the remaining part till it was stuck full of arrows, and then to hang them, they thought those people of the other world …did not exercise this sort of revenge without a meaning…” 

To focus on the faults of the barbarians, one has to turn a blind eye toward their own faults. Montaigne further maintains calling out these people 

“barbarous [is], in respect to the rules of reason: but not in respect to ourselves, who in all sorts of barbarity exceed them. Their wars are throughout noble and generous, and carry as much excuse and fair pretense, as that human malady is capable of; having with them no other foundation than the sole jealousy of valor. Their disputes are not for the conquest of new lands, for these they already possess are so fruitful by nature, as to supply them without labor or concern, with all things necessary, in such abundance that they have no need to enlarge their borders.”  

Thus, they don’t charge weapons against other nations for superficial reasons. They demand their prisoners only an “acknowledgment that they are overcome: but there is not one found in an age, who will not rather choose to die than make such a confession, or either by word or look recede from the entire grandeur of an invincible courage. There is not a man amongst them who had not rather be killed and eaten, than so much as to open his mouth to entreat he may not.” The men thus strive to prove their valor whenever a war situation demands them to. 

Montaigne declares that in the degree of comparison, the Brazilians are savage but they have to be or else it’s the Europeans who are! These people otherwise live in contention without aspiring for anything more. Interestingly, polygamy works well in their culture which for European wives would be unacceptable but if looked through Biblical strictures, is not that big of an issue. 

Lastly, he pronounces the three Brazilians’ possible regret of visiting Europe to gaze at the novelty. They were dumbfounded by the citizen’s adherence to a child (referring to King Charles IX who ascended the throne at a young age) instead of choosing a leader amongst themselves. The second sight of spectacle was witnessing the disparity between the rich and the poor where the latter does not rebel or fight for their rights. 

The essay’s closing statement is ironic at its best when a native chief spills about his visit to the village of his dependence who “planed his paths through the thick of their woods, by which he might pass at his ease” and “they wear no breeches” signifying the lack of façade the barbarians adopt who prefer to be naked and transparent both in attire and their mannerism. 

Of Cannibals | Literary Devices

Brazilians or the inhabitants of the new world are thought of as  “wild fruits”  due to their conditions of living as intimate to nature. 

Flooding of Atlantis 

It is analogous to colonialism where Europe’s thirst for expansion never satiates and revolutions in the later years topple their power and system. 

Montaigne makes an allusion to the 10th century author Suidas who wrote the encyclopedia of the ancient Mediterranean world. 

While Montaigne’s essay speaks about his outlook on the whole debate between civilization and barbarism, it is a matter of contestation that he is too drawing his remarks from the accounts and observations of a man who was a part of the Villegaignon’s landing in Brazil in 1557 which addressed the South American nation the “Antarctic France.” Montaigne, like the rest of the world, is too removed from the immediate reality. 

The Red-Headed League | Summary and Analysis

The laugh of the medusa summary & analysis, related articles.

growing old poem analysis

Growing Old | Summary and Analysis

Love is a fallacy | summary & analysis, in the cemetery where al jolson is buried, a family supper summary & analysis, leave a reply cancel reply.

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

pink bow tie summary and analysis

Adblock Detected

Bookey

The Complete Essays Summary

A journey through inner thoughts and reflections on human nature, michel de montaigne, the art of war, many lives, many masters, brian l. weiss, the power of your subconscious mind, joseph murphy, thinking, fast and slow, daniel kahneman, the art of seduction, robert greene.

michel de montaigne essays summary

Audiobook Online

Description, readers also enjoyed, free pdf download, chapter 1 | overview, chapter 2 | self-knowledge is the foundation of wisdom, and montaigne encourages deep reflection and introspection to cultivate this understanding., chapter 3 | montaigne advocates for embracing uncertainty, questioning conventional wisdom, and embracing the diversity of human experience., chapter 4 | the pursuit of knowledge should not be limited to scholarly pursuits alone; montaigne believes that education should foster moral and ethical growth, leading to a well-lived life., chapter 5 | the complete essays review, books like the complete essays.

michel de montaigne essays summary

The Return of Martin Guerre

Natalie zemon davis, everything you need for every book you read., michel de montaigne quotes in the return of martin guerre.

Identity and Property Theme Icon

Montaigne insists how difficult it is to know the truth about things and how uncertain an instrument is human reason. “Truth and falsehood have both alike countenances…Wee beholde them with one same eye.”

The Nature of Evidence Theme Icon

Literopedia

  • English Literature
  • Short Stories
  • Literary Terms
  • Web Stories

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de Montaigne

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de

Table of Contents

On Some Verses of Virgil by Michel de Montaigne Summary

“On Some Verses of Virgil” is an essay written by Michel de Montaigne , a 16th-century French philosopher and essayist. In this essay, Montaigne reflects on a few selected verses from the works of the Roman poet Virgil and shares his thoughts and interpretations.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Montaigne begins by discussing the power and impact of poetry, asserting that it has the ability to move and inspire readers. He emphasizes the significance of understanding and analyzing poetry in order to fully appreciate its beauty and meaning.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- The essay then focuses on the specific verses from Virgil that Montaigne has chosen to examine. He engages in a close reading of the lines and provides his own commentary and insights. Montaigne delves into the nuances of language and explores the various interpretations and possible meanings behind the words.

  • Against Joie de Vivre Essay Summary By Phillip Lopate
  • The Little Store Essay Summary By Eudora Welty
  • The Search for Marvin Gardens Essay Summary By John McPhee
  • Street Haunting: A London Adventure Essay Summary By Virginia Woolf

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Throughout the essay, Montaigne incorporates personal anecdotes and experiences to further illustrate his points. He relates his own emotional responses to the verses and reflects on the ways in which poetry can resonate with individuals on a deep and personal level.

Montaigne also touches upon the concept of the human condition and the universal themes that Virgil’s poetry explores. He contemplates the nature of love, friendship, and mortality as depicted in the verses, drawing connections to his own observations and philosophical ideas.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- In summary, “On Some Verses of Virgil” is a reflective and analytical essay in which Montaigne explores the power of poetry through the interpretation of selected verses from Virgil. He delves into the language and meaning of the lines, while also incorporating personal experiences and philosophical insights to provide a deeper understanding of the poetic art form.

About Michel de Montaigne

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Michel de Montaigne, born on February 28, 1533, in the Aquitaine region of France, was a philosopher, writer, and essayist. 

He is best known for his collection of essays titled “Essais,” which explored a wide range of topics and made a significant contribution to the development of the essay as a literary form. Montaigne’s writings continue to be studied and appreciated for their introspective nature, humanism, and timeless relevance.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Montaigne was born into a wealthy family and received a classical education. His father, Pierre Eyquem, served as the mayor of Bordeaux, and his mother, Antoinette de Louppes, came from a family of merchants. Montaigne’s early education was influenced by his father’s humanistic beliefs and his exposure to the works of ancient philosophers such as Seneca and Plutarch.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- In 1554, Montaigne began studying law in Toulouse, but he soon abandoned this path, finding the legal profession unfulfilling. Instead, he embarked on a life of contemplation and self-reflection. 

After his father’s death in 1568, Montaigne inherited the family estate and withdrew to his château at Montaigne, where he dedicated himself to reading, writing, and contemplation.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Montaigne’s essays, first published in 1580, are a collection of reflections and observations on a wide variety of subjects, including morality, education, friendship, self-knowledge, and the nature of humanity. The essays were highly personal and often drew from Montaigne’s own experiences and thoughts. He used the essay form as a means of exploring and understanding himself and the world around him.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- One of the central themes in Montaigne’s essays is the concept of skepticism. He questioned the reliability of human knowledge and argued that we should be humble and aware of our limitations. 

Montaigne believed that true wisdom came from recognizing our own ignorance and embracing the uncertainty of the world. This skepticism extended to religious and cultural beliefs as well, and Montaigne advocated for tolerance and open-mindedness in his writings.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Montaigne’s approach to writing was characterized by his conversational style and his use of digressions. He often went off on tangents, exploring related ideas and anecdotes, which gave his essays a meandering quality. 

This approach reflected Montaigne’s belief that the essay should be a free-flowing exploration of thoughts and ideas rather than a rigidly structured argument.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Montaigne’s essays were widely read and admired during his lifetime, and they continue to be studied and celebrated today. His work had a profound influence on the of the essay as a literary genre, and his ideas shaped the thinking of philosophers and writers such as René Descartes, Francis Bacon, and Ralph Waldo Emerson.

Beyond his literary achievements, Montaigne was also involved in public life. He served as a mayor of Bordeaux and as a diplomat, representing the interests of the French crown. However, Montaigne often felt out of place in the political world and expressed a preference for a quiet and contemplative life.

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Montaigne died on September 13, 1592, at the age of 59. His essays have left a lasting legacy, and his ideas continue to resonate with readers around the world. Montaigne’s emphasis on self-exploration, skepticism, and the importance of embracing our own humanity have made him a timeless figure in the history of philosophy and literature.

“On Some Verses of Virgil” by Michel de Montaigne is a thoughtful exploration of the power and meaning of poetry, as exemplified through the analysis of selected verses from the works of Virgil. 

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- Montaigne emphasizes the significance of understanding and appreciating poetry, delving into the nuances of language and exploring various interpretations and meanings behind the words. 

On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de- He relates his own personal experiences and philosophical insights to the verses, providing a deeper understanding of the human condition and universal themes portrayed in Virgil’s poetry. Through this essay, Montaigne invites readers to engage in a contemplative and introspective examination of the artistry and impact of poetic expression.

Q: Who is Michel de Montaigne? 

A: Michel de Montaigne was a 16th-century French philosopher and essayist. He is best known for his collection of essays called “Essais,” in which he explores a wide range of topics and offers personal reflections and insights.

Q: What is the significance of Virgil in Montaigne’s essay? 

A: Virgil, a Roman poet, holds significance in Montaigne’s essay as his verses serve as the subject of analysis and contemplation. Montaigne uses Virgil’s poetry as a starting point to explore the power of language, the depth of human emotions, and the universal themes found in literature.

Q: What is the main idea of Montaigne’s essay? 

A: The main idea of Montaigne’s essay “On Some Verses of Virgil” is to reflect on the power and meaning of poetry. Montaigne engages in a close reading of selected verses from Virgil’s works, providing commentary and personal insights on the language, interpretation, and emotional impact of the poetry. He aims to highlight the importance of understanding and appreciating poetry as a means of connecting with the human experience.

Q: What themes does Montaigne explore in the essay? 

A: Montaigne explores various themes in his essay, including the power of poetry, the nature of language, the complexity of human emotions, and the universal aspects of the human condition. He reflects on themes such as love, friendship, and mortality as depicted in Virgil’s verses, drawing connections to his own experiences and philosophical ideas.

Related Posts

Feelings Are Our Facts Essay by Nick Sturm

Feelings Are Our Facts Essay by Nick Sturm

Reality Is Wild and on the Wing Essay by Steven Moore 

Reality Is Wild and on the Wing Essay by Steven Moore 

A Little World Made Cunningly Essay by Ed Simon

A Little World Made Cunningly Essay by Ed Simon

michel de montaigne essays summary

Attempt a critical appreciation of The Triumph of Life by P.B. Shelley.

Consider The Garden by Andrew Marvell as a didactic poem.

Consider The Garden by Andrew Marvell as a didactic poem.

Why does Plato want the artists to be kept away from the ideal state

Why does Plato want the artists to be kept away from the ideal state

MEG 05 LITERARY CRITICISM & THEORY Solved 2023-24

MEG 05 LITERARY CRITICISM & THEORY Solved Assignment 2023-24

William Shakespeare Biography and Works

William Shakespeare Biography and Works

Discuss the theme of freedom in Frederick Douglass' Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass

Discuss the theme of freedom in Frederick Douglass’ Narrative of the Life of Frederick Douglass

How does William Shakespeare use the concept of power in Richard III

How does William Shakespeare use the concept of power in Richard III

Analyze the use of imagery in William Shakespeare's sonnets

Analyze the use of imagery in William Shakespeare’s sonnets

The title of the first book in j.r.r. tolkien’s “the lord of the rings” series, who wrote “the chronicles of barsetshire” series, shakespeare’s “all the world’s a stage” soliloquy: exploring its significance and legacy, what is the name of the family estate in jane austen’s “pride and prejudice”.

  • Advertisement
  • Privacy & Policy
  • Other Links

© 2023 Literopedia

Welcome Back!

Login to your account below

Remember Me

Retrieve your password

Please enter your username or email address to reset your password.

Are you sure want to unlock this post?

Are you sure want to cancel subscription.

IMAGES

  1. The Complete Essays by Michel de Montaigne

    michel de montaigne essays summary

  2. The Complete Essays of Michel de Montaigne by Michel de Montaigne

    michel de montaigne essays summary

  3. The Essays of Michel de Montaigne (Volume 1 and Handbook [LEC], Volume

    michel de montaigne essays summary

  4. Essays

    michel de montaigne essays summary

  5. Essays of Michel de Montaigne

    michel de montaigne essays summary

  6. Michel de Montaigne

    michel de montaigne essays summary

VIDEO

  1. Citations de Michel De Montaigne

  2. Michel Montaigne

  3. Espaces essayistiques 4. Montaigne: présentation générale

  4. Montaigne's Hardship before Inventing the Essay

  5. The Essays of Michel de Montaigne: That Men by Various Ways Arrive at the Same End (Audiobook)

  6. MICHEL DE MONTAIGNE

COMMENTS

  1. Montaigne: Essays Summary and Study Guide

    Overview. Montaigne: Selected Essays comes from the pen of Michel de Montaigne, a 16th-century French jurist, advisor, and diplomat whose many adventures would make a compelling autobiography. Instead, Montaigne writes a series of short works that examine his innermost thoughts and feelings, attitudes and beliefs, preferences and daily habits.

  2. The Essays Summary

    Summary. Last Updated September 5, 2023. Michel Eyquem de Montaigne was a skeptical philosopher and perhaps the most influential writer of the French Renaissance. His Essays are difficult—maybe ...

  3. Essays (Montaigne)

    The Essays (French: Essais, pronounced) of Michel de Montaigne are contained in three books and 107 chapters of varying length. They were originally written in Middle French and published in the Kingdom of France.Montaigne's stated design in writing, publishing and revising the Essays over the period from approximately 1570 to 1592 was to record "some traits of my character and of my humours."

  4. The Essays of Michel de Montaigne

    Tilde A. Sankovitch. Michel de Montaigne - Renaissance, Essays, Philosopher: Montaigne saw his age as one of dissimulation, corruption, violence, and hypocrisy, and it is therefore not surprising that the point of departure of the Essays is situated in negativity: the negativity of Montaigne's recognition of the rule of appearances and of the ...

  5. Guide to the classics: Michel de Montaigne's Essays

    When Michel de Montaigne retired to his family estate in 1572, aged 38, he tells us that he wanted to write his famous Essays as a distraction for his idle mind.He neither wanted nor expected ...

  6. The Project Gutenberg eBook of Essays of Michel de Montaigne

    The author of the Essays was born, as he informs us himself, between eleven and twelve o'clock in the day, the last of February 1533, at the chateau of St. Michel de Montaigne. His father, Pierre Eyquem, esquire, was successively first Jurat of the town of Bordeaux (1530), Under-Mayor 1536, Jurat for the second time in 1540, Procureur in 1546 ...

  7. Michel de Montaigne

    He received the decoration of the Order of Saint-Michel, a distinction all the more exceptional as Montaigne's lineage was from recent nobility. On the title page of the first edition (1580) of the Essays, we read: "Essais de Messire Michel Seigneur de Montaigne, Chevalier de l'ordre du Roy, & Gentilhomme ordinaire de sa chambre ...

  8. Essays by Michel de Montaigne (Book Analysis)

    This practical and insightful reading guide offers a complete summary and analysis of the Essays, by Michel de Montaigne. It provides a thorough exploration of the essay's plot, context and main themes, including - to list but a few - medicine, knowledge and manners. The clear and concise style makes for easy understanding, providing the ...

  9. Montaigne, Michel de

    Michel de Montaigne, the sixteenth century French essayist, is one of the most renowned literary and philosophical figures of the late Renaissance. The one book he wrote, Les Essais de Michel de Montaigne, is not a traditional work of philosophy. Having begun work on it around 1572, he published the first edition in 1580.

  10. Michel de Montaigne

    Michel de Montaigne (born February 28, 1533, Château de Montaigne, near Bordeaux, France—died September 23, 1592, Château de Montaigne) French writer whose Essais established a new literary form.In his Essays he wrote one of the most captivating and intimate self-portraits ever given, on a par with Augustine's and Rousseau's.. Living, as he did, in the second half of the 16th century ...

  11. The Essays Themes

    Themes of The Essays by Michel de Montaigne include human nature, truth, and proper behavior. Human Nature. Montaigne believes that people are only alive "by chance" and that "no one lays down a ...

  12. Of Cannibals Summary

    Introduction. "Of Cannibals" is an essay by French humanist writer Michel de Montaigne (1533-1592). It was published in 1580 in the first volume of Montaigne's Essays, a collection of ...

  13. Essays of Michel de Montaigne

    Montaigne, Michel de, 1533-1592. Editor. Hazlitt, William Carew, 1834-1913. Translator. Cotton, Charles, 1630-1687. Title. Essays of Michel de Montaigne — Volume 11. Contents. Of judging of the death of another -- That the mind hinders itself -- That our desires are augmented by difficulty -- Of glory -- Of presumption.

  14. The Complete Essays Summary of Key Ideas and Review

    The Complete Essays is a collection of thought-provoking and introspective writings by Michel de Montaigne. Originally published in the 16th century, this book delves into a wide range of topics, from friendship and education to fear and the human experience. Montaigne's unique blend of personal anecdotes, philosophical musings, and historical ...

  15. The Complete Essays

    Michel de Montaigne was one of the most influential figures of the Renaissance, singlehandedly responsible for popularising the essay as a literary form. This Penguin Classics edition of The Complete Essays is translated from the French and edited with an introduction and notes by M.A. Screech.In 1572 Montaigne retired to his estates in order to devote himself to leisure, reading and reflection.

  16. PDF Essays, Book II

    Essays, Book II Michel de Montaigne Glossary braverie: Courage, usually thought of as swaggering courage. colic: This is used to translate colique on page 44 and in essay 37; the OED defines it as 'Acute episodic abdominal pain, especially one arising from the twisting, spasm, or obstruction of a hollow organ'; but as essay 37 proceeds it

  17. Michel de Montaigne summary

    Michel de Montaigne, portrait by an unknown artist, 16th century. Michel de Montaigne, (born Feb. 28, 1533, Château de Montaigne, near Bordeaux, France—died Sept. 23, 1592, Château de Montaigne), French courtier and author. Born into the minor nobility, Montaigne received an excellent Classical education (speaking only Latin up to age 6 ...

  18. Of Cannibals

    Summary of Michel de Montaigne's Of Cannibals. Michel de Montaigne was a renowned 16th-century French philosopher who popularized essay writing as a literary genre and wrote intellectual and thought-provoking essays on human existence and the truths of life. "Of Cannibals" is one of the essays from his 1580 collection of the same name that ...

  19. The Complete Essays Summary PDF

    The Complete Essays by Michel de Montaigne is a thought-provoking exploration that articulates the essence of human experience, captivating us with its profound musings and timeless relevance. With an astute and introspective approach, Montaigne challenges conventional wisdom, inviting readers to embark on an intellectual journey through a vast ...

  20. Michel de Montaigne Character Analysis

    Michel de Montaigne Character Analysis. Michel de Montaigne was a famous Renaissance French writer who coined the term "essay" (French for "to try") in regard to his short writings on various moral and philosophical topics. Like Jean de Coras and Guillaume Le Sueur, Montaigne also witnessed the trial of Martin Guerre at Toulouse.

  21. Of Experience

    In Montaigne's final essay he expounds upon the results of his long search for self knowledge via life experience. He uses disease, health, medicine and doctors as prime arenas for demonstration of what he has learned from living. On physicians: to be a "right" physician, one must have experienced every illness, accident or mishap one seeks to ...

  22. On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de Montaigne

    On Some Verses of Virgil Essay Summary By Michel de-Michel de Montaigne, born on February 28, 1533, in the Aquitaine region of France, was a philosopher, writer, and essayist.He is best known for his collection of essays titled "Essais," which explored a wide range of topics and made a significant contribution to the development of the essay as a literary form.